Library CoqIntro
A streamlined interactive tutorial on fundamentals of Coq,
focusing on a minimal set of features needed for developing
programming language metatheory.
Mostly developed by Aaron Bohannon, with help from Benjamin Pierce, Dimitrios Vytiniotis, and Steve Zdancewic.
Mostly developed by Aaron Bohannon, with help from Benjamin Pierce, Dimitrios Vytiniotis, and Steve Zdancewic.
Contents
- Getting Started
- Definitions
- Proofs
- Working with Implication and Universal Quantification
- Working with Definitions
- Working with Conjunction and Disjunction
- Reasoning by Cases and Induction
- Working with Existential Quantification
- Working with Negation
- Working with Equality
- Reasoning by Inversion
- Additional Important Tactics
- Basic Automation
- Functions and Conversion
- Solutions to Exercises
To get started...
- Install Coq (from the Download page of the main Coq web site)
- Install an IDE: either CoqIDE (from the same page) or Proof General (use Google to find it).
- Which should you choose? Their command sets are similar,
so basically the trade-offs are simple:
- Proof General is an extension of Emacs (or XEmacs, if you prefer), while CoqIDE uses a simpler point-and-click model of editing.
- PG is pretty easy to install; CoqIDE is very easy to install if you can find a pre-built version for the OS you are running on but can be a little tricky to build from scratch because it has lots of dependencies.
- Familiarize yourself with the most important commands
-
- If you are using PG, try this:
- Open this file and check that the mode line says something like "coq Holes Scripting"
- Go down a few pages and do C-C C-return. Notice that the part of the file above the cursor changes color (and becomes read-only), indicating that it has been sent to Coq.
- Come back here and do C-C C-return again
- You now know all you really need to navigate in this file and send parts of it to Coq, but there are some other navigation commands that are sometimes more convenient. To see a couple more, do C-C C-n several times and observe the result; then do C-C C-u a couple of times and observe the result.
- If you are using PG, try this:
-
- If you are using CoqIDE, try this:
- Open this file.
- Scroll down a few pages.
- Hover the mouse over each the buttons at the top of the window; this will make the "tool tips" appear so you can see which is which.
- Press the "Go to cursor" button. Observe what happens.
- Press the forward and backward buttons a few times. Observe.
- Scroll back to here again and start reading.
- If you are using CoqIDE, try this:
- Open the Coq reference manual (from the Documentation page of the Coq web site) in a web browser. Spend 30 seconds looking over the table of contents to get an idea what's there. (There is no need to actually read anything now.)
In this file, we will be working with a very simple language
of expressions over natural numbers and booleans. First we
need to define the datatype of terms.
The
The
Inductive
keyword defines a new inductive type. We
name our new type tm
and declare that tm
lives in the
sort Set
. Types in Set
are datatypes, which can be used
just like those in standard programming languages. After
the inductive definition, the global environment contains
the name of the newly defined type, along with the names of
all of the constructors. Coq also automatically defines a
few operators for eliminating values of the new type
(tm_rec
, tm_ind
, etc.); we can ignore these for the time
being, since we will not need to use them directly.
Inductive tm : Set :=
| tm_true : tm
| tm_false : tm
| tm_if : tm -> tm -> tm -> tm
| tm_zero : tm
| tm_succ : tm -> tm
| tm_pred : tm -> tm
| tm_iszero : tm -> tm.
Next, we want to designate some of our
We define n-ary relations in Coq much as we do on paper -- by giving a set of inference rules that can be used to justify the membership of a tuple in the relation. The definition of such an inference system also uses the keyword
The unary relations
tm
expressions as
"values" in our object language. Mathematically, the
property of being a value is a unary relation over tm
s.
The definition of the unary relation value
will be built
from the definition of two auxiliary relations: bvalue
for
the set of boolean values and nvalue
for the set of
numerical values.
We define n-ary relations in Coq much as we do on paper -- by giving a set of inference rules that can be used to justify the membership of a tuple in the relation. The definition of such an inference system also uses the keyword
Inductive
. Although this is exactly the same device we
used to build the set tm
, in this case we want to do
something slightly different: we will be using it to
inductively defining the structures (derivation trees) that
justify the membership of a tuple in a relation, rather than
directly defining a set inductively. These derivation trees
will need to be given a dependent type in order to ensure
that only correct derivation trees can be built. It is
possible to view their type as a datatype such as tm
;
however, it is more natural to interpret it as a
proposition, so it will be declared to live in Prop
instead of Set
. Prop
is parallel to Set
in the sort
hierarchy, but types in Prop
can be thought of as logical
propositions rather than datatypes. The inhabitants of
types in Prop
can be thought of as proofs rather than
programs.
The unary relations
bvalue
and nvalue
are defined by
very simple inference systems, each having just two rules.
After defining these inference systems, bvalue
and
nvalue
will each be a family of types indexed by elements
of tm
. We can build inhabitants of some (but not all) of
the types in these families with the constructors from our
inductive definition. Semantically, we consider the
proposition bvalue t
to be true if it is inhabited and
false if it is not. (It is worth noting at this point that,
by default, Coq's logic is constructive and P \/ not P
is
provable for some P
but not for others. However, it is
sound to add the law of the excluded middle as an axiom, if
desired.)
Inductive bvalue : tm -> Prop :=
| b_true : bvalue tm_true
| b_false : bvalue tm_false.
Inductive nvalue : tm -> Prop :=
| n_zero : nvalue tm_zero
| n_succ : forall t,
nvalue t ->
nvalue (tm_succ t).
The
Note: It is not actually necessary to provide the types of the arguments nor the return type when they can easily be inferred; for example, the annotations
Definition
keyword is used for defining non-recursive
functions (including 0-ary functions, i.e., constants).
Here we define the unary predicate value
using disjunction
on propositions (written \/
).
Note: It is not actually necessary to provide the types of the arguments nor the return type when they can easily be inferred; for example, the annotations
: tm
and : Prop
are optional here.
Definition value (t : tm) : Prop :=
bvalue t \/ nvalue t.
Having defined
tm
s and value
s, we can define a
call-by-value operational semantics of our language by
giving a definition of the single-step evaluation of one
term to another. We give this as an inductively defined
binary relation.
Inductive eval : tm -> tm -> Prop :=
| e_iftrue : forall t2 t3,
eval (tm_if tm_true t2 t3) t2
| e_iffalse : forall t2 t3,
eval (tm_if tm_false t2 t3) t3
| e_if : forall t1 t1' t2 t3,
eval t1 t1' ->
eval (tm_if t1 t2 t3) (tm_if t1' t2 t3)
| e_succ : forall t t',
eval t t' ->
eval (tm_succ t) (tm_succ t')
| e_predzero :
eval (tm_pred tm_zero) tm_zero
| e_predsucc : forall t,
nvalue t ->
eval (tm_pred (tm_succ t)) t
| e_pred : forall t t',
eval t t' ->
eval (tm_pred t) (tm_pred t')
| e_iszerozero :
eval (tm_iszero tm_zero) tm_true
| e_iszerosucc : forall t,
nvalue t ->
eval (tm_iszero (tm_succ t)) tm_false
| e_iszero : forall t t',
eval t t' ->
eval (tm_iszero t) (tm_iszero t').
We define multi-step evaluation with the relation
eval_many
. This relation includes all of the pairs of
terms that are connected by sequences of evaluation steps.
Inductive eval_many : tm -> tm -> Prop :=
| m_refl : forall t,
eval_many t t
| m_step : forall t t' u,
eval t t' ->
eval_many t' u ->
eval_many t u.
Exercise
Multi-step evaluation is often defined as the "reflexive, transitive closure" of single-step evaluation. Write an inductively defined relationeval_rtc
that corresponds to
that verbal description.
In case you get stuck or need a hint, you can find solutions to all the exercises near the bottom of the file.
A term is a
normal_form
if there is no term to which it
can step. Note the concrete syntax for negation and
existential quantification in the definition below.
Definition normal_form (t : tm) : Prop :=
~ exists t', eval t t'.
Exercise
Sometimes it is more convenient to use a big-step semantics for a language. Add the remaining constructors to finish the inductive definitionfull_eval
for the big-step
semantics that corresponds to the small-step semantics
defined by eval
. Build the inference rules so that
full_eval t v
logically implies both eval_many t v
and
value v
. In order to do this, you may need to add the
premise nvalue v
to the appropriate cases.
Hint: You should end up with a total of 8 cases.
Inductive full_eval : tm -> tm -> Prop := | f_value : forall v, value v -> full_eval v v | f_iftrue : forall t1 t2 t3 v, full_eval t1 tm_true -> full_eval t2 v -> full_eval (tm_if t1 t2 t3) v | f_succ : forall t v, nvalue v -> full_eval t v -> full_eval (tm_succ t) (tm_succ v).
Tip
If you want to see the type of an identifierx
, you can
use the command Check x.
If you want to see the
definition of an identifier x
, you can use the command
Print x.
Check tm_if.
Check m_step.
Check value.
Print value.
A proposition and its proof are both represented as terms in
the calculus of inductive constructions, which is
syntactically very small.
Proof terms are most easily built interactively, using tactics to manipulate a proof state. A proof state consists of a set of goals (propositions or types for which you must produce an inhabitant), each with a context of hypotheses (inhabitants of propositions or types you are allowed to use). A proof state begins initially with one goal (the statement of the lemma you are tying to prove) and no hypotheses. A goal can be solved, and thereby eliminated, when it exactly matches one of hypotheses in the context. A proof is completed when all goals are solved.
Tactics can be used for forward reasoning (which, roughly speaking, means modifying the hypotheses of a context while leaving the goal unchanged) or backward reasoning (replacing the current goal with one or more new goals in simpler contexts). Given the level of detail required in a formal proof, it would be ridiculously impractical to complete a proof using forward reasoning alone. However it is usually both possible and practical to complete a proof using backward reasoning alone. Therefore, we focus almost exclusively on backward reasoning in this tutorial. Of course, most people naturally a significant amount of forward reasoning in their thinking process, so it may take you a while to become accustomed to getting by without it.
We use the keyword
We now proceed to introduce the specific proof tactics.
Proof terms are most easily built interactively, using tactics to manipulate a proof state. A proof state consists of a set of goals (propositions or types for which you must produce an inhabitant), each with a context of hypotheses (inhabitants of propositions or types you are allowed to use). A proof state begins initially with one goal (the statement of the lemma you are tying to prove) and no hypotheses. A goal can be solved, and thereby eliminated, when it exactly matches one of hypotheses in the context. A proof is completed when all goals are solved.
Tactics can be used for forward reasoning (which, roughly speaking, means modifying the hypotheses of a context while leaving the goal unchanged) or backward reasoning (replacing the current goal with one or more new goals in simpler contexts). Given the level of detail required in a formal proof, it would be ridiculously impractical to complete a proof using forward reasoning alone. However it is usually both possible and practical to complete a proof using backward reasoning alone. Therefore, we focus almost exclusively on backward reasoning in this tutorial. Of course, most people naturally a significant amount of forward reasoning in their thinking process, so it may take you a while to become accustomed to getting by without it.
We use the keyword
Lemma
to state a new proposition we
wish to prove. (Theorem
and Fact
are exact synonyms for
Lemma
.) The keyword Proof
, immediately following the
statement of the proposition, indicates the beginning of a
proof script. A proof script is a sequence of tactic
expressions, each concluding with a ".
". Once all of the
goals are solved, we use the keyword Qed
to record the
completed proof. If the proof is incomplete, we may tell
Coq to accept the lemma on faith by using Admitted
instead
of Qed
.
We now proceed to introduce the specific proof tactics.
Example
The tacticintros x1 ... xn
moves antecedents and
universally quantified variables from the goal into the
context as hypotheses. The tactic apply
is complementary
to intros
. If the conclusion (the part following the
rightmost arrow) of a constructor, hypothesis, or lemma e
matches our current goal, then apply e
will replace the
goal with a new goal for each premise/antecedent of e
. If
e
has no premises, then the current goal is solved. Using
apply
allows us to build a proof tree from the bottom up.
In the following example, our proof script will effectively
build the following proof tree:
nvalue t ---------------------------- (e_predsucc) eval (tm_pred (tm_succ t)) t ------------------------------------------------ (e_succ) eval (tm_succ (tm_pred (tm_succ t))) (tm_succ t)
Step through the proof to see how this tree is constructed. For each tactic, we give the corresponding statement in a written proof. (The uses of
Check
are inessential.)
Lemma e_succ_pred_succ : forall t,
nvalue t ->
eval (tm_succ (tm_pred (tm_succ t))) (tm_succ t).
Proof.
Let
t
be a tm
.
intros t.
Assume that
t
is an nvalue
(and let's call that
assumption Hn
for future reference).
intros Hn.
By
e_succ
, in order to prove our conclusion, it suffices
to prove that eval (tm_pred (tm_succ t)) t
.
Check e_succ.
apply e_succ.
That, in turn, can be shown by
e_predsucc
, if we are
able to show that nvalue t
.
Check e_predsucc.
apply e_predsucc.
But, in fact, we assumed
nvalue t
.
apply Hn.
Qed.
Hint for PG users
If you place the cursor afterProof.
and do C-c C-return,
you'll notice that the window displaying Coq's responses is
(annoyingly) empty, instead of showing what is to be proved.
The reason for this is that, actually, a different buffer is
being displayed! (To see this, do C-c C-n and C-c C-u a few
times and notice that the buffer name in the mode line
changes.) You can use C-c C-p to switch the display back
from the *response* buffer to the *goals* buffer.
Example
Now consider, for a moment, the rulem_step
:
eval t t' eval_many t' u ------------------------- (m_step) eval_many t u
If we have a goal such as
eval_many e1 e2
, we should be
able to use apply m_step
in order to replace it with the
goals eval e1 t'
and eval_many t' e2
. But what exactly
is t'
here? When and how is it chosen? It stands to
reason the conclusion is justified if we can come up with
any t'
for which the premises can be justified.
Now we note that, in the Coq syntax for the type of
m_step
, all three variables t
, t'
, and u
are
universally quantified. The tactic apply m_step
will use
pattern matching between our goal and the conclusion of
m_step
to find the only possible instantiation of t
and
u
. However, apply m_step
will raise an error since it
does not know how it should instantiate t'
. In this case,
the apply
tactic takes a with
clause that allows us to
provide this instantiation. This is demonstrated in the
proof below. (Note that the use of this feature means that
our proof scripts are not invariant under alpha-equivalence
on the types of our constructors and lemmas. If this is a
concern, there are other means of achieving the same result
in a way that is compatible with alpha-conversion. See the
next example.)
Observe how this works in the proof script below. The proof tree here gives a visual representation of the proof term we are going to construct and the proof script has again been annotated with the steps in English.
Letting s = tm_succ p = tm_pred lem = e_succ_pred_succ, nvalue t - - - - - - - - - - - - (lem) --------------------- (m_refl) eval (s (p (s t))) (s t) eval_many (s t) (s t) --------------------------------------------------- (m_step) eval_many (s (p (s t))) (s t)
Lemma m_succ_pred_succ : forall t,
nvalue t ->
eval_many (tm_succ (tm_pred (tm_succ t))) (tm_succ t).
Proof.
Let
t
be a tm
, and assume nvalue t
.
intros t Hn.
By
m_step
, to show our conclusion, it suffices to find
some t'
for which
eval (tm_succ (tm_pred (tm_succ t))) t'
and
eval t' (tm_succ t)
.
Let us choose t'
to be tm_succ t
.
Check m_step.
apply m_step with (t' := tm_succ t).
By the lemma
e_succ_pred_succ
, to show
eval (tm_succ (tm_pred (tm_succ t))) (tm_succ t)
,
it suffices to show nvalue t
.
Check e_succ_pred_succ.
apply e_succ_pred_succ.
And, in fact, we assumed
nvluae t
.
apply Hn.
Moreover, by the rule
m_refl
, we also may conclude
eval (tm_succ t) (tm_succ t)
.
Check m_refl.
apply m_refl.
Qed.
Example
Coq is built around the Curry-Howard correspondence. Proofs of universally quantified propositions are functions that take the witness of the quantifier as an argument. Similarly, proofs of implications are functions that take one proof as an argument and return another proof. Observe the types of the following terms.
Check (e_succ_pred_succ).
Check (e_succ_pred_succ tm_zero).
Check (n_zero).
Check (e_succ_pred_succ tm_zero n_zero).
Example
Any tactic likeapply
that takes the name of a constructor
or lemma as an argument can just as easily be given a more
complicated expression as an argument. Thus, we may use
function application to construct proof objects on the fly
in these cases. Observe how this technique can be used to
rewrite the proof of the previous lemma.
Although, we have eliminated one use of
apply
, this is not
necessarily an improvement over the previous proof.
However, there are cases where this technique is quite
valuable.
Lemma m_succ_pred_succ_alt : forall t,
nvalue t ->
eval_many (tm_succ (tm_pred (tm_succ t))) (tm_succ t).
Proof.
intros t Hn.
Check m_step.
apply (m_step
(tm_succ (tm_pred (tm_succ t)))
(tm_succ t)
(tm_succ t)
).
Check e_succ_pred_succ.
apply (e_succ_pred_succ t Hn).
Check m_refl.
apply (m_refl (tm_succ t)).
Qed.
Hint for PG users
By default, the "." key is "electric" -- it inserts a period _and_ causes the material up to the cursor to be sent to Coq. If you find this behavior annoying, it can be toggled by doing "C-c .".
Exercise
Write a proof script to prove the following lemma, based upon the proof given in English.Note: The lemma and the next should be useful in later proofs.
Lemma m_one : forall t1 t2,
eval t1 t2 ->
eval_many t1 t2.
Proof.
Let
t1
and t2
be terms, and assume eval t1 t2
. We
may conclude eval_many t1 t2
by m_step
if we can find
a term t'
such that eval t1 t'
and eval_many t' t2
.
We will choose t'
to be t2
. Now we can show
eval t1 t2
by our assumption, and we can show
eval_many t2 t2
by m_refl
.
Admitted.
Lemma m_two : forall t1 t2 t3,
eval t1 t2 ->
eval t2 t3 ->
eval_many t1 t3.
Proof.
Let
t1
, t2
, and t3
be terms. Assume eval t1 t2
and eval t2 t3
. By m_step
, we may conclude that
eval_many t1 t3
if we can find a term t'
such that
eval t1 t'
and eval_many t' t3
. Let's choose t'
to
be t2
. We know eval t1 t2
holds by assumption. In
the other case, by the lemma m_one
, to show eval_many
t2 t3
, it suffices to show eval t2 t3
, which is one of
our assumptions.
Admitted.
Lemma m_iftrue_step : forall t t1 t2 u,
eval t tm_true ->
eval_many t1 u ->
eval_many (tm_if t t1 t2) u.
Proof.
Let
t
, t1
, t2
, and u
be terms. Assume that
eval t tm_true
and eval_many t1 u
. To show
eval_many (tm_if t t1 t2) u
, by m_step
, it suffices to
find a t'
for which eval (tm_if t t1 t2) t'
and
eval_many t' u
. Let us choose t'
to be
tm_if tm_true t1 t2
. Now we can use e_if
to show that
eval (tm_if t t1 t2) (tm_if tm_true t1 t2)
if we can
show eval t tm_true
, which is actually one of our
assumptions. Moreover, using m_step
once more, we can
show eval_many (tm_if tm_true t1 t2) u
where t'
is
chosen to be t1
. Doing so leaves us to show
eval (tm_if tm_true t1 t2) t1
and eval_many t1 u
. The
former holds by e_iftrue
and the latter holds by
assumption.
Admitted.
Example
There is a notion of equivalence on Coq terms that arises from the conversion rules of the underlying calculus of constructions. It is sometimes useful to be able to replace one term in a proof with an equivalent one. For instance, we may want to replace a defined name with its definition. This sort of replacement can be done the tacticunfold
.
This tactic can be used to manipulate the goal or the
hypotheses.
Definition strongly_diverges t :=
forall u, eval_many t u -> ~ normal_form u.
Lemma unfold_example : forall t t',
strongly_diverges t ->
eval t t' ->
strongly_diverges t'.
Proof.
intros t t' Hd He.
unfold strongly_diverges. intros u Hm.
unfold strongly_diverges in Hd.
apply Hd. apply m_step with (t' := t').
apply He.
apply Hm.
Qed.
Exercise
In reality, many tactics will perform conversion automatically as necessary. Try removing the uses ofunfold
from the above proof to check which ones were
necessary.
Working with Conjunction and Disjunction
-
split
-
left
-
right
-
destruct
(for conjunction and disjunction)
Example
IfH
is the name of a conjunctive hypothesis, then
destruct H as p
will replace the hypothesis H
with its
components using the names in the pattern p
. Observe the
pattern in the example below.
Lemma m_two_conj : forall t t' t'',
eval t t' /\ eval t' t'' ->
eval_many t t''.
Proof.
intros t t' t'' H.
destruct H as [ He1 He2 ].
apply m_two with (t2 := t').
apply He1.
apply He2.
Qed.
Example
Patterns may be nested to break apart nested structures. Note that infix conjunction is right-associative, which is significant when trying to write nested patterns. We will later see how to usedestruct
on many different sorts of
hypotheses.
Lemma m_three_conj : forall t t' t'' t''',
eval t t' /\ eval t' t'' /\ eval t'' t''' ->
eval_many t t'''.
Proof.
intros t t' t'' t''' H.
destruct H as [ He1 [ He2 He3 ] ].
apply m_step with (t' := t').
apply He1.
apply m_two with (t2 := t'').
apply He2.
apply He3.
Qed.
Lemma m_three : forall t t' t'' t''',
eval t t' ->
eval t' t'' ->
eval t'' t''' ->
eval_many t t'''.
Proof.
intros t t' t'' t''' He1 He2 He3.
apply m_three_conj with (t' := t') (t'' := t'').
split.
apply He1.
split.
apply He2.
apply He3.
Qed.
Lemma m_if_iszero_conj : forall v t2 t2' t3 t3',
nvalue v /\ eval t2 t2' /\ eval t3 t3' ->
eval_many (tm_if (tm_iszero tm_zero) t2 t3) t2' /\
eval_many (tm_if (tm_iszero (tm_succ v)) t2 t3) t3'.
Proof.
Admitted.
Example
If the goal is a disjunction, we can use theleft
or
right
tactics to solve it by proving the left or right
side of the conclusion.
Lemma true_and_succ_zero_values :
value tm_true /\ value (tm_succ tm_zero).
Proof.
unfold value. split.
left. apply b_true.
right. apply n_succ. apply n_zero.
Qed.
Example
If we have a disjunction in the context, we can usedestruct
to reason by cases on the hypothesis. Note the
syntax of the associated pattern.
Lemma e_if_true_or_false : forall t1 t2,
eval t1 tm_true \/ eval t1 tm_false ->
eval_many (tm_if t1 t2 t2) t2.
Proof.
intros t1 t2 H. destruct H as [ He1 | He2 ].
apply m_two with (t2 := tm_if tm_true t2 t2).
apply e_if. apply He1.
apply e_iftrue.
apply m_two with (t2 := tm_if tm_false t2 t2).
apply e_if. apply He2.
apply e_iffalse.
Qed.
Lemma two_values : forall t u,
value t /\ value u ->
bvalue t \/
bvalue u \/
(nvalue t /\ nvalue u).
Proof.
We know
value t
and value u
, which means either
bvalue t
or nvalue t
, and either bvalue u
or
nvalue u
. Consider the case in which
bvalue t
holds. Then one of the disjuncts of our
conclusion is proved. Next, consider the case in which
nvalue t
holds. Now consider the subcase where
bvalue u
holds. ...
Admitted.
Example
destruct
can be used on propositions with implications.
This will have the effect of performing destruct
on the
conclusion of the implication, while leaving the hypotheses
of the implication as additional subgoals.
Lemma destruct_example : forall bv t t' t'',
bvalue bv ->
(value bv -> eval t t' /\ eval t' t'') ->
eval_many t t''.
Proof.
intros bv t t' t'' Hbv H. destruct H as [ H1 H2 ].
Show 2.
unfold value. left. apply Hbv.
apply m_two with (t2 := t').
apply H1.
apply H2.
Qed.
Tip
After applying a tactic that introduces multiple subgoals, it is sometimes useful to see not only the subgoals themselves but also their hypotheses. Adding the commandShow n.
to your proof script to cause Coq to display the
nth subgoal in full.
Example
Usedestruct
to reason by cases on an inductively defined
datatype or proposition.
Note: It is possible to supply
destruct
with a pattern in
these instances also. However, the patterns become
increasingly complex for bigger inductive definitions; so it
is often more practical to omit the pattern (thereby letting
Coq choose the names of the terms and hypotheses in each
case), in spite of the fact that this adds an element of
fragility to the proof script (since the proof script will
mention names that were system-generated).
Lemma e_iszero_nvalue : forall v,
nvalue v ->
eval (tm_iszero v) tm_true \/
eval (tm_iszero v) tm_false.
Proof.
intros v Hn. destruct Hn.
left. apply e_iszerozero.
right. apply e_iszerosucc. apply Hn.
Qed.
Example
You can useinduction
to reason by induction on an
inductively defined datatype or proposition. This is the
same as destruct
, except that it also introduces an
induction hypothesis in the inductive cases.
Lemma m_iszero : forall t u,
eval_many t u ->
eval_many (tm_iszero t) (tm_iszero u).
Proof.
intros t u Hm. induction Hm.
apply m_refl.
apply m_step with (t' := tm_iszero t').
apply e_iszero. apply H.
apply IHHm.
Qed.
Lemma m_trans : forall t t' u,
eval_many t t' ->
eval_many t' u ->
eval_many t u.
Proof.
We proceed by induction on the derivation of
eval_many t t'
.
Case m_refl
: Since t
and t'
must be the same, our
conclusion holds by assumption.
Case m_step
: Now let's rename the t'
from the lemma
statement to u0
(as Coq likely will) and observe that
there must be some t'
(from above the line of the
m_step
rule) such that eval t t'
and
eval_many t' u0
. Our conclusion follows from from
an application of m_step
with our new t'
and our
induction hypothesis, which allows us to piece together
eval_many t' u0
and eval_many u0 u
to get
eval_many t' u
.
Admitted.
Exercise
It is possible to usedestruct
not just on hypotheses but
on any lemma we have proved. If we have a lemma
lemma1 : P /\ Q
then we can use the tactic
destruct lemma1 as [ H1 H2 ].
to continue our proof with
H1 : P
and H2 : Q
in our
context. This works even if the lemma has antecedents (they
become new subgoals); however it fail if the lemma has a
universal quantifier, such as this:
lemma2 : forall x, P(x) /\ Q(x)
However, remember that we can build a proof of
P(e) /\ Q(e)
(which can be destructed) using the Coq
expression lemma2 e
. So we need to phrase our tactic as
destruct (lemma2 e) as [ H1 H2 ].
An example of this technique is below.
Lemma m_iszero_nvalue : forall t v,
nvalue v ->
eval_many t v ->
eval_many (tm_iszero t) tm_true \/
eval_many (tm_iszero t) tm_false.
Proof.
intros t v Hnv Hm.
destruct (e_iszero_nvalue v) as [ H1 | H2 ].
apply Hnv.
left. apply m_trans with (t' := tm_iszero v).
apply m_iszero. apply Hm.
apply m_one. apply H1.
right. apply m_trans with (t' := tm_iszero v).
apply m_iszero. apply Hm.
apply m_one. apply H2.
Qed.
Exercise
Prove the following lemma.Hint: You may be interested in some previously proved lemmas, such as
m_one
and m_trans
.
Note: Even though this lemma is in a comment, its solution is also at the bottom. (Coq will give an error if we leave it uncommented since it mentions the
eval_rtc
relation,
which was the solution to another exercise.)
Lemma eval_rtc_many : forall t u, eval_rtc t u -> eval_many t u.
Exercise
Prove the following lemma.Lemma eval_many_rtc : forall t u, eval_many t u -> eval_rtc t u.
Exercise
Prove the following lemma.Lemma full_eval_to_value : forall t v, full_eval t v -> value v.
Lemma if_bvalue : forall t1 t2 t3,
bvalue t1 ->
exists u, eval (tm_if t1 t2 t3) u.
Proof.
intros t1 t2 t3 Hb. destruct Hb.
exists t2. apply e_iftrue.
exists t3. apply e_iffalse.
Qed.
Lemma m_two_exists : forall t u,
(exists w, eval t w /\ eval w u) ->
eval_many t u.
Proof.
intros t u H.
destruct H as [ w He ].
destruct He as [ He1 He2 ].
apply m_two with (t2 := w).
apply He1.
apply He2.
Qed.
Example
Tip: We can combine patterns that destruct existentials with patterns that destruct other logical connectives.Here is the same proof with just one use of
destruct
.
Lemma m_two_exists' : forall t u,
(exists w, eval t w /\ eval w u) ->
eval_many t u.
Proof.
intros t u H. destruct H as [ w [ He1 He2 ] ].
apply m_two with (t2 := w).
apply He1.
apply He2.
Qed.
Example
Tip: We give patterns to theintros
tactic to destruct
hypotheses as we introduce them.
Here is the same proof again without any uses of
destruct
.
Lemma m_two_exists'' : forall t u,
(exists w, eval t w /\ eval w u) ->
eval_many t u.
Proof.
intros t u [ w [ He1 He2 ] ].
apply m_two with (t2 := w).
apply He1.
apply He2.
Qed.
Lemma value_can_expand : forall v,
value v ->
exists u, eval u v.
Proof.
Admitted.
Exercise
Tip: You should find the lemmam_iszero
useful. Use
Check m_iszero.
if you've forgotten its statement.
Lemma exists_iszero_nvalue : forall t,
(exists nv, nvalue nv /\ eval_many t nv) ->
exists bv, eval_many (tm_iszero t) bv.
Proof.
There exists some
nv
such that nvalue nv
. Consider
the case where nv
is tm_zero
. Then choose bv
to
be tm_true
. By m_trans
, we can show that
eval_many (tm_iszero t) tm_true
by showing
eval_many (tm_iszero t) (tm_iszero tm_zero)
and
eval_many (tm_iszero tm_zero) tm_true
. The former
follows from m_iszero
and our assumption. The latter
follows from m_one
and the rule e_iszerozero
. On the
other hand, in the case where nv
is built from
tm_succ
, we choose bv
to be tm_false
and the proof
follows similarly.
Admitted.
Example
The standard library defines an uninhabited typeFalse
and
defines not P
to stand for P -> False
. Furthermore, Coq
defines the notation ~ P
to stand for not P
. (Such
notations only affect parsing and printing -- Coq views not
P
and ~ P
as being syntactically equal.)
The most basic way to work with negated statements is to unfold
not
and treat False
just as any other
proposition.
(Note how multiple definitions can be unfolded with one use of
unfold
. Also, as noted earlier, many uses of unfold
are not strictly necessary. You can try deleting the uses
from the proof below to check that the proof script still
works.)
Lemma normal_form_succ : forall t,
normal_form (tm_succ t) ->
normal_form t.
Proof.
intros t Hnf.
unfold normal_form. unfold not.
unfold normal_form, not in Hnf.
intros [ t' H' ]. apply Hnf.
exists (tm_succ t'). apply e_succ. apply H'.
Qed.
Lemma normal_form_to_forall : forall t,
normal_form t ->
forall u, ~ eval t u.
Proof.
Admitted.
Lemma normal_form_from_forall : forall t,
(forall u, ~ eval t u) ->
normal_form t.
Proof.
Admitted.
Example
If you happen to haveFalse
as a hypothesis, you may use
destruct
on that hypothesis to solve your goal.
Lemma False_hypothesis : forall v,
False ->
value v.
Proof.
intros v H. destruct H.
Qed.
Example
Recalling thatdestruct
can be used on propositions with
antecedents and that negation is simply an abbreviation for
an implication, using destruct
on a negated hypothesis has
the derived behavior of replacing our goal with the
proposition that was negated in our context.
Tip: We actually don't even need to do the unfolding below because
destruct
would have done it for us.
Lemma destruct_negation_example : forall t v,
value v ->
eval t tm_zero ->
(value v -> normal_form t) ->
eval tm_true tm_false.
Proof.
intros t v Hnv He Hnf.
unfold normal_form, not in Hnf.
destruct Hnf.
apply Hnv.
exists tm_zero. apply He.
Qed.
Lemma negation_exercise : forall v1 v2,
~ (value v1 \/ value v2) ->
~ (~ bvalue v1 /\ ~ bvalue v2) ->
eval tm_true tm_false.
Proof.
Admitted.
Example
If you have an equality in your context, there are several ways to substitute one side of the equality for the other in your goal or in other hypotheses.If one side of the equality is a variable
x
, then the
tactic subst x
will replace all occurrences of x
in the
context and goal with the other side of the quality and will
remove x
from your context.
Use
reflexivity
to solve a goal of the form e = e
.
Lemma equality_example_1 : forall t1 t2 t3 u1 u2,
t1 = tm_iszero u1 ->
t2 = tm_succ u2 ->
t3 = tm_succ t2 ->
tm_if t1 t2 t3 =
tm_if (tm_iszero u1) (tm_succ u2) (tm_succ (tm_succ u2)).
Proof.
intros t1 t2 t3 u1 u2 Heq1 Heq2 Heq3.
subst t1. subst t2. subst t3. reflexivity.
Qed.
Example
If neither side of the equality in your context is a variable (or if you don't want to discard the hypothesis), you can use therewrite
tactic to perform a substitution.
The arrow after rewrite
indicates the direction of the
substitution. As demonstrated, you may perform rewriting in
the goal or in a hypothesis.
Lemma equality_example_2a : forall t u v,
tm_succ t = tm_succ u ->
eval (tm_succ u) v ->
eval (tm_succ t) v.
Proof.
intros t u v Heq He. rewrite -> Heq. apply He.
Qed.
Lemma equality_example_2b : forall t u v,
tm_succ t = tm_succ u ->
eval (tm_succ u) v ->
eval (tm_succ t) v.
Proof.
intros t u v Heq He. rewrite <- Heq in He. apply He.
Qed.
Example
We also note that, analogously withdestruct
, we may use
rewrite
even with a hypothesis (or lemma) that has
antecedents.
Lemma equality_example_2c : forall t u v,
nvalue v ->
(nvalue v -> tm_succ t = tm_succ u) ->
eval (tm_succ u) v ->
eval (tm_succ t) v.
Proof.
intros t u v Hnv Heq He. rewrite <- Heq in He.
apply He.
apply Hnv.
Qed.
Example
If you need to derive additional equalities implied by an equality in your context (e.g., by the principle of constructor injectivity), you may useinversion
.
inversion
is a powerful tactic that uses unification to
introduce more equalities into your context. (You will
observe that it also performs some substitutions in your
goal.)
Lemma equality_example_3 : forall t u,
tm_succ t = tm_succ u ->
t = u.
Proof.
intros t u Heq. inversion Heq. reflexivity.
Qed.
Lemma equality_exercise : forall t1 t2 t3 u1 u2 u3 u4,
tm_if t1 t2 t3 = tm_if u1 u2 u2 ->
tm_if t1 t2 t3 = tm_if u3 u3 u4 ->
t1 = u4.
Proof.
Admitted.
Example
inversion
will also solve a goal when unification fails on
a hypothesis. (Internally, Coq can construct a proof of
False
from contradictory equalities.)
Lemma equality_example_4 :
tm_zero = tm_true ->
eval tm_true tm_false.
Proof.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
Qed.
Exercise
Note:e1 <> e2
is a notation for ~ e1 = e2
, i.e., the
two are treated as syntactically equal.
Note: This is fairly trivial to prove if we have a size function on terms and some automation. With just the tools we have described so far, it requires just a little bit of work.
Hint: The proof requires induction on
t
. (This is the
first example of induction on datatypes, but it is even more
straightforward than induction on propositions.) In each
case, unfold the negation, pull the equality into the
context, and use inversion
to eliminate contradictory
equalities.
Lemma succ_not_circular : forall t,
t <> tm_succ t.
Proof.
Admitted.
Example
Theinversion
tactic also allows you to reason by
inversion on an inductively defined proposition as in paper
proofs: we try to match some proposition with the conclusion
of each inference rule and only consider the cases (possibly
none) where there is a successful unification. In those
cases, we may use the premises of the inference rule in our
reasoning.
Since
inversion
may generate many equalities between
variables, it is useful to know that using subst
without
an argument will perform all possible substitutions for
variables. It is a little difficult to predict which
variables will be eliminated and which will be kept by this
tactic, but this is a typical sort of trade-off when using
powerful tactics.
(The use of
subst
in this proof is superfluous, but you
can observe that it simplifies the context.)
Lemma value_succ_nvalue : forall t,
value (tm_succ t) ->
nvalue t.
Proof.
intros t H. unfold value in H. destruct H as [ H1 | H2 ].
inversion H1.
inversion H2. subst. apply H0.
Qed.
Lemma inversion_exercise : forall t,
normal_form t ->
eval_many (tm_pred t) tm_zero ->
nvalue t.
Proof.
By inversion on the By
By
have By
contradicts our assumption that
eval_many
relation, then conclusion
eval_many (tm_pred t) tm_zero
must have been derived by
the rule m_step
, which means there is some t'
for
which eval (tm_pred t) t'
and eval_many t' tm_zero
.
Now, by inversion on the eval
relation, there are only
three ways that eval (tm_pred t) t'
could have been
derived:
By e_predzero
, with t
and t'
both being equal to
tm_zero
. Our conclusion follows from n_zero
.
By e_predsucc
, with t
being tm_succ t0
where we
have nvalue t0
. In this case, our conclusion is
provable with n_succ
.
By e_pred
, with t
taking an evaluation step. This
contradicts our assumption that t
is a normal form
(which can be shown by using destruct
on that
assumption).
Admitted.
Lemma contradictory_equalities_exercise :
(exists t, exists u, exists v,
value t /\
t = tm_succ u /\
u = tm_pred v) ->
eval tm_true tm_false.
Proof.
Admitted.
Lemma eval_fact_exercise : forall t1 t2,
eval (tm_iszero (tm_pred t1)) t2 ->
eval t2 tm_false ->
exists u, t1 = tm_succ u.
Proof.
Admitted.
Lemma normal_form_if : forall t1 t2 t3,
normal_form (tm_if t1 t2 t3) ->
t1 <> tm_true /\ t1 <> tm_false /\ normal_form t1.
Proof.
Admitted.
Example
Sometimes we need to have a tactic that moves hypotheses from our context back into our goal. Often this is because we want to perform induction in the middle of a proof and will not get a sufficiently general induction hypothesis without a goal of the correct form. (To be specific, if we need to have an induction hypothesis with aforall
quantifier in front, then we must make sure our
goal has a forall
quantifier in front at the time we
invoke the induction
tactic.) Observe how generalize
dependent
achieves this in the proof below, moving the
variable t
and all dependent hypotheses back into the
goal. You may want to remove the use of generalize
dependent
to convince yourself that it is performing an
essential role here.
Lemma value_is_normal_form : forall v,
value v ->
normal_form v.
Proof.
intros v [ Hb | Hn ] [ t He ].
destruct Hb.
inversion He.
inversion He.
generalize dependent t. induction Hn.
intros t He. inversion He.
intros u He. inversion He. subst. destruct (IHHn t').
apply H0.
Qed.
Exercise
Coq has many operations (called "tacticals") to combine smaller tactics into larger ones.If
t1
and t2
are tactics, then t1; t2
is a tactic that
executes t1
, and then executes t2
on subgoals left by or
newly generated by t1
. This can help to eliminate
repetitious use of tactics. Two idiomatic uses are
performing subst
after inversion
and performing intros
after induction
. More opportunities to use this tactical
can usually be discovered after writing a proof. (It is
worth noting that some uses of this tactical can make proofs
less readable or more difficult to maintain. Alternatively,
some uses can make proofs more readable or easier to
maintain. It is always good to think about your priorities
when writing a proof script.)
Revise the proof for
value_is_normal_form
to include uses
of the ;
tactical.
Example
Sometimes it is helpful to be able to use forward reasoning in a proof. One form of forward reasoning can be done with the tacticassert
. assert
adds a new hypothesis to the
context but asks us to first justify it.
Lemma nvalue_is_normal_form : forall v,
nvalue v ->
normal_form v.
Proof.
intros v Hnv.
assert (value v) as Hv. right. apply Hnv.
apply value_is_normal_form. apply Hv.
Qed.
Example
assert
can also be supplied with a tactic that proves the
assertion. We rewrite the above proof using this form.
Lemma nvalue_is_normal_form' : forall v,
nvalue v ->
normal_form v.
Proof.
intros v Hnv.
assert (value v) as Hv by (right; apply Hnv).
apply value_is_normal_form. apply Hv.
Qed.
Example
The proof below introduces two new, simple tactics. First, the tacticreplace e1 with e2
performs a substitution in
the goal and then requires that you prove e2 = e1
as a new
subgoal. This often allows us to avoid more cumbersome
forms of forward reasoning. Second, the clear
tactic
discards a hypothesis from the context. Of course, this
tactic is never needed, but it can be nice to use when there
are complicated, irrelevant hypotheses in the context.
Lemma single_step_to_multi_step_determinacy :
(forall t u1 u2, eval t u1 -> eval t u2 -> u1 = u2) ->
forall t v1 v2,
eval_many t v1 -> normal_form v1 ->
eval_many t v2 -> normal_form v2 ->
v1 = v2.
Proof.
intros H t v1 v2 Hm1 Hnf1 Hm2 Hnf2. induction Hm1.
clear H. destruct Hm2.
reflexivity.
destruct Hnf1. exists t'. apply H.
destruct Hm2.
destruct Hnf2. exists t'. apply H0.
apply IHHm1; clear IHHm1.
apply Hnf1.
replace t' with t'0.
apply Hm2.
apply H with (t := t).
apply H1.
apply H0.
Qed.
Exercise
This proof is lengthy and thus somewhat challenging. All of the techniques from this section will be useful; some will be essential. In particular, you will need to usegeneralize dependent
at the beginning of the proof. You
will find assert
helpful in the cases where your
assumptions are contradictory but none of them are in a
negative form. In that situation, you can assert a negative
statement that follows from your hypotheses (recall that
normal_form
is a negative statement). Finally, you will
want to use the above lemma nvalue_is_normal_form
. Good
luck!
Theorem eval_deterministic : forall t t' t'',
eval t t' ->
eval t t'' ->
t' = t''.
Proof.
Admitted.
Exercise
Prove the following lemmas. The last is quite long, and you may wish to wait until you know more about automation.Lemma full_eval_from_value : forall v w, value v -> full_eval v w -> v = w. Lemma eval_full_eval : forall t t' v, eval t t' -> full_eval t' v -> full_eval t v. Lemma full_eval_complete : forall t v, value v -> eval_many t v -> full_eval t v.
Example
You can useeapply e
instead of apply e with (x := e1)
.
This will generate subgoals containing unification variables
that will get unified during subsequent uses of apply
.
Lemma m_if : forall t1 u1 t2 t3,
eval_many t1 u1 ->
eval_many (tm_if t1 t2 t3) (tm_if u1 t2 t3).
Proof.
intros t1 u1 t2 t3 Hm. induction Hm.
apply m_refl.
eapply m_step.
apply e_if. apply H.
apply IHHm.
Qed.
Example
You can useesplit
to turn an existentially quantified
variable in your goal into a unification variable.
Lemma exists_pred_zero :
exists u, eval (tm_pred tm_zero) u.
Proof.
esplit. apply e_predzero.
Qed.
Example
Theauto
tactic solves goals that are solvable by any
combination of
-
intros
-
apply
(used on some local hypothesis) -
split
,left
,right
-
reflexivity
If
auto
cannot solve the goal, it will leave the proof
state completely unchanged (without generating any errors).
The lemma below is a proposition that has been contrived for the sake of demonstrating the scope of the
auto
tactic and
does not say anything of practical interest. So instead of
thinking about what it means, you should think about the
operations that auto
had to perform to solve the goal.
Note: It is important to remember that
auto
does not
destruct hypotheses! There are more advanced forms of
automation available that do destruct hypotheses in some
specific ways.
Lemma auto_example : forall t t' t'',
eval t t' ->
eval t' t'' ->
(forall u, eval t t' -> eval t' u -> eval_many t u) ->
eval t' t \/ t = t /\ eval_many t t''.
Proof.
auto.
Qed.
Example
Theeauto
tactic solves goals that are solvable by some
combination of
-
intros
-
eapply
(used on some local hypothesis) -
split
,left
,right
-
esplit
-
reflexivity
This lemma has two significantly differences from the previous one, both of which render
auto
useless.
Lemma eauto_example : forall t t' t'',
eval t t' ->
eval t' t'' ->
(forall u, eval t u -> eval u t'' -> eval_many t t'') ->
eval t' t \/ (exists u, t = u) /\ eval_many t t''.
Proof.
eauto.
Qed.
Example
You can enhanceauto
(or eauto
) by appending using x_1,
..., x_n
, where each x_i
is the name of some constructor
or lemma. Then auto
will attempt to apply those
constructors or lemmas in addition to the assumptions in
the local context.
Lemma eauto_using_example : forall t t' t'',
eval t t' ->
eval t' t'' ->
eval t' t \/ t = t /\ eval_many t t''.
Proof.
eauto using m_step, m_one.
Qed.
Exercise
Go back and rewrite your proofs form_one
, m_two
, and
m_iftrue_step
. You should be able to make them very
succinct given what you know now.
Exercise
See how short you can make these proofs.Note: This is an exercise. We are not making the claim that shorter proofs are necessarily better!
Hint: Remember that we can connect tactics in sequence with
;
. However, as you can imagine, figuring out the best
thing to write after a ;
usually involves some trial and
error.
Lemma pred_not_circular : forall t,
t <> tm_pred t.
Proof.
Admitted.
Lemma m_succ : forall t u,
eval_many t u ->
eval_many (tm_succ t) (tm_succ u).
Proof.
Admitted.
Lemma m_pred : forall t u,
eval_many t u ->
eval_many (tm_pred t) (tm_pred u).
Proof.
Admitted.
Exercise
Go back and rewrite your proofs form_trans
and
two_values
. Pulling together several tricks you've
learned, you should be able to prove two_values
in one
(short) line.
Note
Sometimes there are lemmas or constructors that are so frequently needed byauto
that we don't want to have to
add them to our using
clause each time. Coq allows us to
request that certain propositions that always be
considered by auto
and eauto
.
The following command adds four lemmas to the default search procedure of
auto
.
Hint Resolve m_if m_succ m_pred m_iszero.
Constructors of inductively defined propositions are some of
the most frequently needed by
we may simply write
Let's add all our constructors to
auto
. Instead of writing
Hint Resolve b_true b_false.
we may simply write
Hint Constructors bvalue.
Let's add all our constructors to
auto
.
Hint Constructors bvalue nvalue eval eval_many.
By default
auto
will never try to unfold definitions to
see if a lemma or constructor can be applied. With the
Hint Unfold
command, we can instruct auto
to try unfold
definitions in the goal as it is working.
Hint Unfold value normal_form.
There are a few more variants on the
Hint
command that can
be used to further customize auto
. You can learn about
them in the Coq reference manual.
Functions and Conversion
-
Fixpoint/struct
-
match ... end
-
if ... then ... else ...
-
simpl
-
remember
In this section we start to use Coq as a programming language and learn how to reason about programs defined within Coq.
Example
Coq defines many datatypes in its standard libraries. Have a quick look now through the libraryDatatypes
to see some
of the basic ones, in particular bool
and nat
. (Note
that constructors of the datatype nat
are the letter O
and the letter S
. However, Coq will parse and print
nat
s using a standard decimal representation.)
We define two more datatypes here that will be useful later.
Inductive bool_option : Set :=
| some_bool : bool -> bool_option
| no_bool : bool_option.
Inductive nat_option : Set :=
| some_nat : nat -> nat_option
| no_nat : nat_option.
Example
We can define simple (non-recursive) functions from one datatype to another using theDefinition
keyword. The
match
construct allows us to do case analysis on a
datatype. The match
expression has a first-match
semantics and allows nested patterns; however, Coq's type
checker demands that pattern-matching be exhaustive.
We define functions below for converting between Coq
bool
s
and boolean values in our object language.
Definition tm_to_bool (t : tm) : bool_option :=
match t with
| tm_true => some_bool true
| tm_false => some_bool false
| _ => no_bool
end.
Definition bool_to_tm (b : bool) : tm :=
match b with
| true => tm_true
| false => tm_false
end.
Example
Coq also has anif/then/else
expression. It can be used,
not just with the type bool
but, in fact, with any
datatype having exactly two constructors (the first
constructor corresponding to the then
branch and the
second to the else
branch). Thus, we can define a
function is_bool
as below.
Definition is_bool (t : tm) : bool :=
if tm_to_bool t then true else false.
Example
To define a recursive function, useFixpoint
instead of
Definition
.
The type system will only allow us to write functions that terminate. The annotation
{struct t}
here informs the
type-checker that termination is guaranteed because the
function is being defined by structural recursion on t
.
Fixpoint tm_to_nat (t : tm) {struct t} : nat_option :=
match t with
| tm_zero => some_nat O
| tm_succ t1 =>
match tm_to_nat t1 with
| some_nat n => some_nat (S n)
| no_nat => no_nat
end
| _ => no_nat
end.
Fixpoint nat_to_tm (n : nat) {struct n} : tm :=
match n with
| O => tm_zero
| S m => tm_succ (nat_to_tm m)
end.
Exercise
Write a functioninterp : tm -> tm
that returns the
normal form of its argument according to the small-step
semantics given by eval
.
Hint: You will want to use
tm_to_nat
(or another auxiliary
function) to prevent stuck terms from stepping in the cases
e_predsucc
and e_iszerosucc
.
Example
The tacticsimpl
(recursively) reduces the application of
a function defined by pattern-matching to an argument with a
constructor at its head. You can supply simpl
with a
particular expression if you want to prevent it from
simplifying elsewhere.
Lemma bool_tm_bool : forall b,
tm_to_bool (bool_to_tm b) = some_bool b.
Proof.
intros b. destruct b.
simpl (bool_to_tm true). simpl. reflexivity.
reflexivity.
Qed.
Lemma tm_bool_tm :forall t b,
tm_to_bool t = some_bool b ->
bool_to_tm b = t.
Proof.
intros t b Heq. destruct t.
simpl in Heq. inversion Heq.
simpl. reflexivity.
inversion Heq. reflexivity.
simpl in Heq. inversion Heq.
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq.
Qed.
Lemma tm_to_bool_dom_includes_bvalue : forall bv,
bvalue bv -> exists b, tm_to_bool bv = some_bool b.
Proof.
Admitted.
Lemma tm_to_bool_dom_only_bvalue : forall bv b,
tm_to_bool bv = some_bool b -> bvalue bv.
Proof.
Admitted.
Example
Not all uses ofsimpl
are optional. Sometimes they are
necessary so that we can use the rewrite
tactic. Observe,
also, how using rewrite
can automatically trigger a
reduction if it creates a redex.
Lemma nat_tm_nat : forall n,
tm_to_nat (nat_to_tm n) = some_nat n.
Proof.
intros n. induction n.
reflexivity.
simpl. rewrite -> IHn. reflexivity.
Qed.
Example
Here's an example where it is necessary to usesimpl
on a
hypothesis. To trigger a reduction of a match
expression
in a hypothesis, we use the destruct
tactic on the
expression being matched.
Lemma tm_nat_tm : forall t n,
tm_to_nat t = some_nat n ->
nat_to_tm n = t.
Proof.
intros t. induction t; intros n Heq.
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq. reflexivity.
simpl in Heq. destruct (tm_to_nat t).
inversion Heq. simpl. rewrite -> IHt.
reflexivity.
reflexivity.
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq.
Qed.
Lemma tm_to_nat_dom_includes_nvalue : forall v,
nvalue v -> exists n, tm_to_nat v = some_nat n.
Proof.
Admitted.
Lemma tm_to_nat_dom_only_nvalue : forall v n,
tm_to_nat v = some_nat n -> nvalue v.
Proof.
Admitted.
Example
Using the tacticdestruct
(or induction
) on a complex
expression (i.e., one that is not simply a variable) may not
leave you with enough information for you to finish the
proof. The tactic remember
can help in these cases. Its
usage is demonstrated below. If you are curious, try to
finish the proof without remember
to see what goes wrong.
Lemma remember_example : forall v,
eval_many
(tm_pred (tm_succ v))
(match tm_to_nat v with
| some_nat _ => v
| no_nat => tm_pred (tm_succ v)
end).
Proof.
intros v. remember (tm_to_nat v) as x. destruct x.
apply m_one. apply e_predsucc.
eapply tm_to_nat_dom_only_nvalue.
rewrite <- Heqx. reflexivity.
apply m_refl.
Qed.
Exercise
Prove the following lemmas involving the functioninterp
from a previous exercise:
Lemma interp_reduces : forall t, eval_many t (interp t). Lemma interp_fully_reduces : forall t, normal_form (interp t).
Inductive eval_rtc : tm -> tm -> Prop :=
| r_eval : forall t t',
eval t t' ->
eval_rtc t t'
| r_refl : forall t,
eval_rtc t t
| r_trans : forall t u v,
eval_rtc t u ->
eval_rtc u v ->
eval_rtc t v.
Inductive full_eval : tm -> tm -> Prop :=
| f_value : forall v,
value v ->
full_eval v v
| f_iftrue : forall t1 t2 t3 v,
full_eval t1 tm_true ->
full_eval t2 v ->
full_eval (tm_if t1 t2 t3) v
| f_iffalse : forall t1 t2 t3 v,
full_eval t1 tm_false ->
full_eval t3 v ->
full_eval (tm_if t1 t2 t3) v
| f_succ : forall t v,
nvalue v ->
full_eval t v ->
full_eval (tm_succ t) (tm_succ v)
| f_predzero : forall t,
full_eval t tm_zero ->
full_eval (tm_pred t) tm_zero
| f_predsucc : forall t v,
nvalue v ->
full_eval t (tm_succ v) ->
full_eval (tm_pred t) v
| f_iszerozero : forall t,
full_eval t tm_zero ->
full_eval (tm_iszero t) tm_true
| f_iszerosucc : forall t v,
nvalue v ->
full_eval t (tm_succ v) ->
full_eval (tm_iszero t) tm_false.
Lemma m_one_sol : forall t t',
eval t t' ->
eval_many t t'.
Proof.
intros t t' He. apply m_step with (t' := t').
apply He.
apply m_refl.
Qed.
Lemma m_two_sol : forall t t' t'',
eval t t' ->
eval t' t'' ->
eval_many t t''.
Proof.
intros t t' t'' He1 He2. apply m_step with (t' := t').
apply He1.
apply m_one. apply He2.
Qed.
Lemma m_iftrue_step_sol : forall t t1 t2 u,
eval t tm_true ->
eval_many t1 u ->
eval_many (tm_if t t1 t2) u.
Proof.
intros t t1 t2 u He Hm.
apply m_step with (t' := tm_if tm_true t1 t2).
apply e_if. apply He.
apply m_step with (t' := t1).
apply e_iftrue.
apply Hm.
Qed.
Lemma m_if_iszero_conj_sol : forall v t2 t2' t3 t3',
nvalue v /\ eval t2 t2' /\ eval t3 t3' ->
eval_many (tm_if (tm_iszero tm_zero) t2 t3) t2' /\
eval_many (tm_if (tm_iszero (tm_succ v)) t2 t3) t3'.
Proof.
intros v t2 t2' t3 t3' H.
destruct H as [ Hn [ He1 He2 ] ]. split.
apply m_three with
(t' := tm_if tm_true t2 t3) (t'' := t2).
apply e_if. apply e_iszerozero.
apply e_iftrue.
apply He1.
apply m_three with
(t' := tm_if tm_false t2 t3) (t'' := t3).
apply e_if. apply e_iszerosucc. apply Hn.
apply e_iffalse.
apply He2.
Qed.
Lemma two_values_sol : forall t u,
value t /\ value u ->
bvalue t \/
bvalue u \/
(nvalue t /\ nvalue u).
Proof.
unfold value. intros t u H.
destruct H as [ [ Hb1 | Hn1 ] H2 ].
left. apply Hb1.
destruct H2 as [ Hb2 | Hn2 ].
right. left. apply Hb2.
right. right. split.
apply Hn1.
apply Hn2.
Qed.
Lemma m_trans_sol : forall t u v,
eval_many t u ->
eval_many u v ->
eval_many t v.
Proof.
intros t u v Hm1 Hm2. induction Hm1.
apply Hm2.
apply m_step with (t' := t').
apply H.
apply IHHm1. apply Hm2.
Qed.
Lemma eval_rtc_many_sol : forall t u,
eval_rtc t u ->
eval_many t u.
Proof.
intros t u Hr. induction Hr.
apply m_one. apply H.
apply m_refl.
apply m_trans with (t' := u).
apply IHHr1.
apply IHHr2.
Qed.
Lemma eval_many_rtc_sol : forall t u,
eval_many t u ->
eval_rtc t u.
Proof.
intros t u Hm. induction Hm.
apply r_refl.
apply r_trans with (u := t').
apply r_eval. apply H.
apply IHHm.
Qed.
Lemma full_eval_to_value_sol : forall t v,
full_eval t v ->
value v.
Proof.
intros t v Hf. induction Hf.
apply H.
apply IHHf2.
apply IHHf2.
right. apply n_succ. apply H.
right. apply n_zero.
right. apply H.
left. apply b_true.
left. apply b_false.
Qed.
Lemma value_can_expand_sol : forall v,
value v ->
exists u, eval u v.
Proof.
intros v Hv. exists (tm_if tm_true v v). apply e_iftrue.
Qed.
Lemma exists_iszero_nvalue_sol : forall t,
(exists nv, nvalue nv /\ eval_many t nv) ->
exists bv, eval_many (tm_iszero t) bv.
Proof.
intros t [ nv [ Hnv Hm ]]. destruct Hnv.
exists tm_true.
apply m_trans with (t' := tm_iszero tm_zero).
apply m_iszero. apply Hm.
apply m_one. apply e_iszerozero.
exists tm_false.
apply m_trans with (t' := tm_iszero (tm_succ t0)).
apply m_iszero. apply Hm.
apply m_one. apply e_iszerosucc. apply Hnv.
Qed.
Lemma normal_form_to_forall_sol : forall t,
normal_form t ->
forall u, ~ eval t u.
Proof.
unfold normal_form, not. intros t H u He.
apply H. exists u. apply He.
Qed.
Lemma normal_form_from_forall_sol : forall t,
(forall u, ~ eval t u) ->
normal_form t.
Proof.
unfold normal_form, not. intros t H [ t' Het' ].
apply H with (u := t'). apply Het'.
Qed.
Lemma negation_exercise_sol : forall v1 v2,
~ (value v1 \/ value v2) ->
~ (~ bvalue v1 /\ ~ bvalue v2) ->
eval tm_true tm_false.
Proof.
intros v1 v2 H1 H2. destruct H2.
split.
intros Hb. destruct H1. left. left. apply Hb.
intros Hb. destruct H1. right. left. apply Hb.
Qed.
Lemma equality_exercise_sol : forall t1 t2 t3 u1 u2 u3 u4,
tm_if t1 t2 t3 = tm_if u1 u2 u2 ->
tm_if t1 t2 t3 = tm_if u3 u3 u4 ->
t1 = u4.
Proof.
intros t1 t2 t3 u1 u2 u3 u4 Heq1 Heq2.
inversion Heq1. subst t1. subst t2. subst t3.
inversion Heq2. reflexivity.
Qed.
Lemma succ_not_circular_sol : forall t,
t <> tm_succ t.
Proof.
intros t. induction t.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
intros Heq. inversion Heq. destruct IHt. apply H0.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
Qed.
Lemma inversion_exercise_sol : forall t,
normal_form t ->
eval_many (tm_pred t) tm_zero ->
nvalue t.
Proof.
intros t Hnf Hm. inversion Hm. subst. inversion H.
apply n_zero.
apply n_succ. apply H2.
destruct Hnf. exists t'0. apply H2.
Qed.
Lemma contradictory_equalities_exercise_sol :
(exists t, exists u, exists v,
value t /\
t = tm_succ u /\
u = tm_pred v) ->
eval tm_true tm_false.
Proof.
intros [ t [ u [ v [ [ Hb | Hn ] [ eq1 eq2 ] ] ] ] ].
destruct Hb.
inversion eq1.
inversion eq1.
destruct Hn.
inversion eq1.
inversion eq1. subst t. subst u. inversion Hn.
Qed.
Lemma eval_fact_exercise_sol : forall t1 t2,
eval (tm_iszero (tm_pred t1)) t2 ->
eval t2 tm_false ->
exists u, t1 = tm_succ u.
Proof.
intros t1 t2 He1 He2. inversion He1. subst t2.
inversion He2. subst t'.
inversion H0. exists (tm_succ t0). reflexivity.
Qed.
Lemma normal_form_if_sol : forall t1 t2 t3,
normal_form (tm_if t1 t2 t3) ->
t1 <> tm_true /\ t1 <> tm_false /\ normal_form t1.
Proof.
intros t1 t2 t3 Hnf. destruct t1.
destruct Hnf. exists t2. apply e_iftrue.
destruct Hnf. exists t3. apply e_iffalse.
split.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
split.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
intros [t' He]. destruct Hnf. exists (tm_if t' t2 t3).
apply e_if. apply He.
split.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
split.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
intros [t' He]. inversion He.
split.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
split.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
intros [t' He]. destruct Hnf. exists (tm_if t' t2 t3).
apply e_if. apply He.
split.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
split.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
intros [t' He]. destruct Hnf. exists (tm_if t' t2 t3).
apply e_if. apply He.
split.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
split.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
intros [t' He]. destruct Hnf. exists (tm_if t' t2 t3).
apply e_if. apply He.
Qed.
Lemma full_eval_from_value_sol : forall v w,
value v ->
full_eval v w ->
v = w.
Proof.
intros v w Hv Hf. induction Hf.
reflexivity.
destruct Hv as [ Hb | Hn ].
inversion Hb.
inversion Hn.
destruct Hv as [ Hb | Hn ].
inversion Hb.
inversion Hn.
rewrite -> IHHf.
reflexivity.
right. apply value_succ_nvalue. apply Hv.
destruct Hv as [ Hb | Hn ].
inversion Hb.
inversion Hn.
destruct Hv as [ Hb | Hn ].
inversion Hb.
inversion Hn.
destruct Hv as [ Hb | Hn ].
inversion Hb.
inversion Hn.
destruct Hv as [ Hb | Hn ].
inversion Hb.
inversion Hn.
Qed.
Lemma value_is_normal_form_sol : forall v,
value v ->
normal_form v.
Proof.
intros v [ Hb | Hn ] [ t He ].
destruct Hb; inversion He.
generalize dependent t.
induction Hn; intros u He; inversion He; subst.
destruct (IHHn t'). apply H0.
Qed.
Theorem eval_deterministic_sol : forall t t' t'',
eval t t' ->
eval t t'' ->
t' = t''.
Proof.
intros t t' t'' He1. generalize dependent t''.
induction He1; intros t'' He2; inversion He2; subst.
reflexivity.
inversion H3.
reflexivity.
inversion H3.
inversion He1.
inversion He1.
rewrite -> (IHHe1 t1'0).
reflexivity.
apply H3.
rewrite -> (IHHe1 t'0).
reflexivity.
apply H0.
reflexivity.
inversion H0.
reflexivity.
assert (normal_form (tm_succ t)) as Hnf.
apply nvalue_is_normal_form. apply n_succ. apply H.
destruct Hnf. exists t'. apply H1.
inversion He1.
assert (normal_form (tm_succ t'')) as Hnf.
apply nvalue_is_normal_form. apply n_succ. apply H0.
destruct Hnf. exists t'. apply He1.
rewrite -> (IHHe1 t'0).
reflexivity.
apply H0.
reflexivity.
inversion H0.
reflexivity.
assert (normal_form (tm_succ t)) as Hnf.
apply nvalue_is_normal_form. apply n_succ. apply H.
destruct Hnf. exists t'. apply H1.
inversion He1.
assert (normal_form (tm_succ t0)) as Hnf.
apply nvalue_is_normal_form. apply n_succ. apply H0.
destruct Hnf. exists t'. apply He1.
rewrite -> (IHHe1 t'0).
reflexivity.
apply H0.
Qed.
Lemma eval_full_eval_sol : forall t t' v,
eval t t' ->
full_eval t' v ->
full_eval t v.
Proof.
intros t t' v He. generalize dependent v. induction He.
intros v Hf. apply f_iftrue.
apply f_value. left. apply b_true.
apply Hf.
intros v Hf. apply f_iffalse.
apply f_value. left. apply b_false.
apply Hf.
intros v Hf. inversion Hf.
subst. inversion H.
inversion H0.
inversion H0.
subst. apply f_iftrue.
apply IHHe. apply H3.
apply H4.
subst. apply f_iffalse.
apply IHHe. apply H3.
apply H4.
intros v Hf. inversion Hf.
subst. apply f_succ.
apply value_succ_nvalue. apply H.
apply IHHe. apply f_value. right.
apply value_succ_nvalue. apply H.
subst. apply f_succ.
apply H0.
apply IHHe. apply H1.
intros v Hf. inversion Hf. apply f_predzero.
apply f_value. right. apply n_zero.
intros v Hf. assert (t = v).
apply full_eval_from_value_sol.
right. apply H.
apply Hf.
subst v. apply f_predsucc.
apply H.
apply f_succ.
apply H.
apply Hf.
intros v Hf. inversion Hf.
subst. destruct H as [ Hb | Hn ].
inversion Hb.
inversion Hn.
subst. apply f_predzero. apply IHHe. apply H0.
subst. apply f_predsucc.
apply H0.
apply IHHe. apply H1.
intros v Hf. inversion Hf. apply f_iszerozero.
apply f_value. right. apply n_zero.
intros v Hf. inversion Hf.
apply f_iszerosucc with (v := t).
apply H.
apply f_value. right. apply n_succ. apply H.
intros v Hf. inversion Hf.
subst. destruct H as [ Hb | Hn ].
inversion Hb.
inversion Hn.
subst. apply f_iszerozero. apply IHHe. apply H0.
subst. apply f_iszerosucc with (v := v0).
apply H0.
apply IHHe. apply H1.
Qed.
Lemma full_eval_complete_sol : forall t v,
value v ->
eval_many t v ->
full_eval t v.
Proof.
intros t v Hv Hm. induction Hm.
apply f_value. apply Hv.
apply eval_full_eval_sol with (t' := t').
apply H.
apply IHHm. apply Hv.
Qed.
Lemma pred_not_circular_sol : forall t,
t <> tm_pred t.
Proof.
intros t H. induction t; inversion H; auto.
Qed.
Lemma m_succ_sol : forall t u,
eval_many t u ->
eval_many (tm_succ t) (tm_succ u).
Proof.
intros t u Hm.
induction Hm; eauto using m_refl, m_step, e_succ.
Qed.
Lemma m_pred_sol : forall t u,
eval_many t u ->
eval_many (tm_pred t) (tm_pred u).
Proof.
intros t u Hm.
induction Hm; eauto using m_refl, m_step, e_pred.
Qed.
Fixpoint interp (t : tm) {struct t} : tm :=
match t with
| tm_true => tm_true
| tm_false => tm_false
| tm_if t1 t2 t3 =>
match interp t1 with
| tm_true => interp t2
| tm_false => interp t3
| t4 => tm_if t4 t2 t3
end
| tm_zero => tm_zero
| tm_succ t1 => tm_succ (interp t1)
| tm_pred t1 =>
match interp t1 with
| tm_zero => tm_zero
| tm_succ t2 =>
match tm_to_nat t2 with
| some_nat _ => t2
| no_nat => tm_pred (tm_succ t2)
end
| t2 => tm_pred t2
end
| tm_iszero t1 =>
match interp t1 with
| tm_zero => tm_true
| tm_succ t2 =>
match tm_to_nat t2 with
| some_nat _ => tm_false
| no_nat => tm_iszero (tm_succ t2)
end
| t2 => tm_iszero t2
end
end.
Lemma tm_to_bool_dom_includes_bvalue_sol : forall bv,
bvalue bv -> exists b, tm_to_bool bv = some_bool b.
Proof.
intros bv H. destruct H.
exists true. reflexivity.
exists false. reflexivity.
Qed.
Lemma tm_to_bool_dom_only_bvalue_sol : forall bv b,
tm_to_bool bv = some_bool b -> bvalue bv.
Proof.
intros bv b Heq. destruct bv.
apply b_true.
apply b_false.
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq.
Qed.
Lemma tm_to_nat_dom_includes_nvalue_sol : forall v,
nvalue v -> exists n, tm_to_nat v = some_nat n.
Proof.
intros v Hnv. induction Hnv.
exists O. reflexivity.
destruct IHHnv as [ n Heq ]. exists (S n).
simpl. rewrite -> Heq. reflexivity.
Qed.
Lemma tm_to_nat_dom_only_nvalue_sol : forall v n,
tm_to_nat v = some_nat n -> nvalue v.
Proof.
intros v. induction v; intros n Heq.
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq.
apply n_zero.
apply n_succ.
simpl in Heq. destruct (tm_to_nat v).
inversion Heq. eapply IHv. reflexivity.
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq.
Qed.
Lemma interp_reduces_sol : forall t,
eval_many t (interp t).
Proof.
intros t. induction t.
apply m_refl.
apply m_refl.
simpl. destruct (interp t1).
eapply m_trans.
apply m_if. apply IHt1.
eapply m_trans.
eapply m_one. apply e_iftrue.
apply IHt2.
eapply m_trans.
apply m_if. apply IHt1.
eapply m_trans.
eapply m_one. apply e_iffalse.
apply IHt3.
apply m_if. apply IHt1.
apply m_if. apply IHt1.
apply m_if. apply IHt1.
apply m_if. apply IHt1.
apply m_if. apply IHt1.
apply m_refl.
simpl. apply m_succ. apply IHt.
simpl. destruct (interp t).
apply m_pred. apply IHt.
apply m_pred. apply IHt.
apply m_pred. apply IHt.
eapply m_trans.
apply m_pred. apply IHt.
apply m_one. apply e_predzero.
remember (tm_to_nat t0) as x. destruct x.
eapply m_trans.
apply m_pred. apply IHt.
apply m_one. apply e_predsucc.
eapply tm_to_nat_dom_only_nvalue.
rewrite <- Heqx. reflexivity.
apply m_pred. apply IHt.
apply m_pred. apply IHt.
apply m_pred. apply IHt.
simpl. destruct (interp t).
apply m_iszero. apply IHt.
apply m_iszero. apply IHt.
apply m_iszero. apply IHt.
eapply m_trans.
apply m_iszero. apply IHt.
apply m_one. apply e_iszerozero.
remember (tm_to_nat t0) as x. destruct x.
eapply m_trans.
apply m_iszero. apply IHt.
apply m_one. apply e_iszerosucc.
eapply tm_to_nat_dom_only_nvalue.
rewrite <- Heqx. reflexivity.
apply m_iszero. apply IHt.
apply m_iszero. apply IHt.
apply m_iszero. apply IHt.
Qed.
Lemma interp_fully_reduces_sol : forall t,
normal_form (interp t).
Proof.
induction t; intros [t' H].
inversion H.
inversion H.
simpl in H. destruct (interp t1).
destruct IHt2. eauto.
destruct IHt3. eauto.
destruct IHt1. inversion H. eauto.
destruct IHt1. inversion H. eauto.
destruct IHt1. inversion H. eauto.
destruct IHt1. inversion H. eauto.
destruct IHt1. inversion H. eauto.
inversion H.
destruct IHt. inversion H. eauto.
simpl in H. destruct (interp t).
inversion H. inversion H1.
inversion H. inversion H1.
inversion H. destruct IHt. eauto.
inversion H.
remember (tm_to_nat t0) as x. destruct x.
destruct IHt. exists (tm_succ t').
apply e_succ. apply H.
inversion H; subst.
destruct (tm_to_nat_dom_includes_nvalue t')
as [n Heq].
apply H1.
rewrite <- Heqx in Heq. inversion Heq.
destruct IHt. eauto.
inversion H. destruct IHt. eauto.
inversion H. destruct IHt. eauto.
simpl in H. destruct (interp t).
inversion H. inversion H1.
inversion H. inversion H1.
inversion H. destruct IHt. eauto.
inversion H.
remember (tm_to_nat t0) as x. destruct x.
inversion H.
inversion H; subst.
destruct (tm_to_nat_dom_includes_nvalue t0)
as [n Heq].
apply H1.
rewrite <- Heqx in Heq. inversion Heq.
inversion H. destruct IHt. eauto.
inversion H. destruct IHt. eauto.
inversion H. destruct IHt. eauto.
Qed.